Most Read... John McAuliffeBill Manhire in Conversation with John McAuliffe
(PN Review 259)
Patricia CraigVal Warner: A Reminiscence
(PN Review 259)
Eavan BolandA Lyric Voice at Bay
(PN Review 121)
Joshua WeinerAn Exchange with Daniel Tiffany/Fall 2020
(PN Review 259)
Vahni CapildeoOn Judging Prizes, & Reading More than Six Really Good Books
(PN Review 237)
Christopher MiddletonNotes on a Viking Prow
(PN Review 10)
Next Issue Kirsty Gunn re-arranges the world John McAuliffe reads Seamus Heaney's letters and translations Chris Price's 'Songs of Allegiance' David Herman on Aharon Appelfeld Victoria Moul on Christopher Childers compendious Greek and Latin Lyric Book Philip Terry again answers the question, 'What is Poetry'
Poems Articles Interviews Reports Reviews Contributors
Reader Survey
PN Review Substack

This article is taken from PN Review 268, Volume 49 Number 2, November - December 2022.

Universals and Particulars Robert Griffiths
The world is made up of particulars. So, if one were trying to represent that world in writing one might hope to capture something of that particularity. One might do this by referring to an immediate sensory experience: ‘I heard a cough / as if a thief were there…’ (Alice Oswald, Fox), or to a specific object, in a specific context:
It was the first gift he ever gave her,
buying it for five francs in the Galeries
in pre-war Paris...
(Eavan Boland, The Black Lace Fan My Mother Gave Me)
In this way, particularity seems important, perhaps even crucial to certain kinds of poems.

Plato, the first ever literary critic, nevertheless decided that it was a profound weakness in poetry that it was too preoccupied with particulars, and not enough with the universal. He thought of a poet as representing, for example, only a particular love, and not the universal, LOVE. The latter, apparently more important thing, he saw as the concern of the philosopher.

In a very obvious way, though, Plato could not have been more mistaken about the character of poetry. For poets are users of words, and words, as was noted by a much later philosopher, do not refer to particulars. They refer only to universals. John Locke, the eighteenth-century philosopher who wrote the first sustained treatise on the nature of language, was puzzled by this oddity – that while the world consisted of particulars, the vast majority of words signified universals: ‘All things, that exist, being particulars, it may perhaps be thought reasonable that words, which ought to ...


Searching, please wait... animated waiting image